In what way do the Elements exist in the Mixtum?



back to homepage


Introduction

We already explored this subject in the Essay The Mixtum and its Elements in a thematical way. In the present Essay we will put more emphasis on the relevant classical texts devoted to the problem of the ontological status of the elements of a mixtum (With the term "mixtum" (plural : mixta), we will denote any more ore less complex entity that can be considered as consisting, in one way or another, of "elements").
The problem of the way in which elements exist in mixta everytime recurs when we want to investigate the ontological status of a complex entity. That's the reason why it pops up almost everywhere on this website. It is an important problem because it decides whether there are, or are not, complex entities, existing in their own right as genuine beings which cannot be totally identified with their elements, i.e. complex entities, for which one cannot say that they just ARE their constituents (elements), although they do not contain anything else besides those elements. This implies that the being of the elements of such complex entities is weakened in some way :   the elements do not actually exist anymore, only the mixtum exists. Of course not just any mixtum will satisfy this state of affairs, but some do, it seems, and these are the genuine "Totalities". Such a Totality is ONE genuine being, although it is not simple, but consists of elements (See also the two Essays on Totalities : The Totality, or uniform Thing and What is a Totality?). These elements come in several types or grades. If we consider for example a multicellular organism, then we can say that it is a Totality, i.e. a totality of elements. These elements are first of all its organs. But organs cannot strictly be seen as stable entities that interact, and in so doing generate and constitute the organism, because organs themselves change during the individual existence of the organism, as is clearly visible in the case of the embryological development, and especially in the case of metamorphosis like we see in the individual developement of certain insects. All the organs are made up however of cells, and the cell seems to be the fundamental unit, the fundamental element of a living being. However, also cells change during the individual life of an organism, also visible in embryogenesis and metamorphosis. The same can be said of the molecules constituting the organism. Finally we come to the atoms that make up those molecules (while some are feely existing in the organism, often in the form of single electrically charged atoms. Indeed atoms, insofar as they reside in organisms, do not change identity (they do so only in nuclear reactions or in processes of nuclear decay -- radioactivity), they stay the same specifically (not individually : individual atoms are often replaced by other individuals). So it seems reasonable to consider the atoms (i.e. the relevant atomic species, represented by atomic individuals) as the genuine elements ("elements", not necessarily in a chemical sense, i.e. as such they are not solely the elements of chemical compounds) of an organism (organic mixtum). By forming certain configurations (dynamic as well as more or less static), they constitute the organism, the organismic Totality. The same applies to the other Totalities (considered on this website) :   molecules and crystals. They also can be considered as mixta, of which the elements are atoms.

The Way of Being of the Elements in the Mixtum

Let us start with a text of St Thomas in his Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle : In VII Met. lectio 16, nr. 1631--1636 (We will make use of the translation by John P. ROWAN, 1961) (comments in square brackets):
nr. 1631.
"Here the Philosopher [ by "the Philosopher" is always meant : Aristotle ] clears up a point which remained a difficulty above, namely, how a substance is composed of parts, when he showed above that a substance could be composed neither of its accidental attributes nor of actually existing substances. Therefore he shows here that the parts of which substances are composed are not actually existing substances but potential ones. He says that, since it was stated above that there are some things which are thought by all to be substances, namely sensible substances and their parts, it is evident that most substances of this kind are potential and not actual, as is clear of the parts of animals and all other parts.
nr. 1632.
He says that the parts of these substances are many, because since each whole is composed of many parts, there must be more component parts than composite wholes. And it is evident that parts exist potentially, because none of them are separate, but all parts as parts are rather united in the whole.
nr. 1633.
For everything which is actual must be distinct from other things, because one thing is distinguished from another by its own actuality and form, as was stated above. But when those things which are assumed to be parts have been separated from each other when the whole is dissolved, they are then actual beings, not as parts but as matter existing under the privation of the form of the whole. This is evident, for example, of earth, fire and air, which, when they are parts of a compound, are not actually existing things but exist potentially in the compound. But when they are separated, they are then actually existing things and not parts. For none of the elements "before they are arranged," i.e., before they reach their proper state of mixture by way of alteration, and before one compound comes from them, together form a unity, except in the sense that a heap of stones is one in a qualified sense and not in an unqualified one. Or better "none of them," i.e., they do not constitute a unity before some one thing is produced from them by arrangement.
nr. 1634.
For even though all parts exist potentially, someone might very readily suppose that the parts of living things and those of the soul [ I continue here with a corrected translation, after having signalled an error in the ROWAN translation of this sentence : are close [ to their act ], implying that they are considered as in act and [ also ] as in potency ], i.e. they are in potentiality close to actuality. And the reason is that living bodies are organic bodies having parts which are formally distinct. Hence they most of all are close to being actual. And this is because they have a principle of motion in some determinate part, since one part moves another. This is clear, for instance, in the case of their joints, in which the principle of motion of one of the two connected parts seems to be found, since one can be moved and another at rest, as is stated in The Motion of Animals.
nr. 1635.
And since not only the parts of the body are in potentiality close to actuality, but also the parts of the soul, therefore some animals live after they have been divided, as segmented animals. And this is possible because in the whole animal there is one soul actually and there are many souls potentially. But when division is made the several souls become actual. This happens because of the imperfection of such animals which require very little diversity in their parts, for they have a soul with imperfect ability to function and incapable of acting in different ways, for which a number of different organs are necessary.
nr. 1636.
Yet even though these parts of the soul and the parts of living things are close to actuality, nevertheless they are all potential when the whole is one and continuous by nature. But this would not be the case if one thing came into being by force, as, for example, when the parts of one living thing are tied to those of another, or by grafting, as happens in the case of plants. For before the scion which is to be inserted is united with the plant, it is actual, but afterwards it is potential. "For such a thing," namely, to be one by force or grafting, "is a mutilation," i.e., something injurious to nature and opposed to nature."
About the mixtum and its elements St Thomas (or perhaps, pseudo Thomas) also writes in De Natura Materiae et Dimensionibus Interminatis, namely in Chapter 9, just after its beginning.
Some other places where St Thomas treats of this subject are : In VIII Met. lectio 3, nr. 1712--1714, and In VII Met. lectio 13, nr. 1588.

What is the ontological status of the elements in a mixtum, in this case a genuine mixtum (not a mixture), for example a molecule of a chemical compound, a crystal or an organism?
In Scholastic texts (as for examlple St Thomas') one poses that if the elements are actually present in a mixtum, then this is not a genuine mixtum, but an aggregate. So in a genuine mixtum the elements would only be virtually present.
Again we have the problem of being-a-Totality.
In In VII Met. lectio 14, nr. 1598, St Thomas distinguishes three kinds of physical 'joining together' (merging), which he makes clear by the following examples (on which I give some further comments):

  1. "Per compositionem", like a house that is built from (separate) bricks (stones). The result is a (non-accidental) aggregate of more or less separate components.
  2. "Per copulationem" (= fixing, fastening), like a box is made from nailed-together pieces of wood. This is an aggregate too, be it that in this case the components are being held together by internal forces (here elastic forces).
  3. "Per mixtionem" (= by mixing), like an electarium (= a medicine that melts in the mouth) that is generated from changed materials (substances, in the ordinary (chemical) sense). This is undoubtedly what we today call a chemical reaction between reagents, resulting -- in this case -- in a chemical compound. This is the "mixtum perfectum"
About the ontological status (the way of being) of the elements in the mixtum and outside this mixtum, the following is said, at the end of Chapter 8 of the treatise De Natura Materiae et Dimensionibus Interminatis :
"It is however certain that in a part, that is separated from the whole, a substantial form is present : that's why the part is, [ as residing ] in its whole, in a potency that has maximally approached its act, because it is impossible to assume a dual substantial being in the same thing, as is said above, [ and because one ] also [ should ] not [ assume such a dual substantial being ] as a consequence of one or another preceding change, [ and because one ] also [ should ] not [ assume ] that a new form is induced, unless through a change."
The new form of the part is not induced until by a change, i.e. when the mixtum has been subjected to a change, in such a way that it has been disintegrated into its parts, which then have become actual.
This in fact is a description of a heterogeneous continuum. In the text this is expounded mainly by those states of affairs which we find in living beings, because in those days inorganic mixta were perhaps considered as homogeneous. Nowadays however, these, for instance chemical compounds, have turned out to be heterogeneous either. This, on the basis of chemical and X-ray analysis of such compounds.
For instance, it is certain that in crystals of chemical compounds the atomic nuclei are completely conserved, including their properties (for example any radioactivity). Also the inner 'shells' of the atoms of a crystal are (in the case of more or less heavy chemical elements) conserved, and with them their properties, for instance the X-ray spectrum.
So if the initial elements, that were to make up such a compound, were different from the outset, then at least some of these differences will be conserved in the (crystal of the) compound, causing it to be heterogeneous.
It is perhaps possible to interpret all these findings in the following way :
The observed properties of the parts (elements) are, in the mixtum, (now) properties OF THE MIXTUM, which -- how could it be otherwise -- are very similar to the properties of the elements before they were united into the mixtum perfectum.
Of course this must be investigated.

Homogeneous and Heterogeneous Continua

Above we noticed that inorganic substances were considered as homogeneous continua in the days of St Thomas (quite understandable, when one beholds chemical compounds, for example in the form of crystals).
At about the middle of Chapter 9 of the treatise De Natura Materiae et Dimensionibus Interminatis indeed homogeneous and heterogeneous continua are being treated of.
In the case of homogeneous continua a multitude of beings is generated by the process of division, beings, which are specifically the same, and also specifically the same as the initial continuum before division. This is said to be the case in inorganic substances and lower organisms. If indeed such a continuum is constituted by a repetition of conspecific unities, within one integral whole, then it is clear that division will give rise to several beings which are conspecific with that continuum before division. This is the case in crystals : They consist of a periodic repetition in three directions of a unit cell. Fission results in several beings idem specie ( = while the species remains the same)( NOTE 1 ). Also in the case of some animals (The treatise mentions articulated animals) like Earthworms (Annelida) a repetition of units can be observed, but in this case in one direction only, they form a chain of identical metamers (with a weakly pronounced differentiation of the front end). These animals seem to be idem specie divisible.
There are however animals which can be divided idem specie because of their ability of regeneration, for example Flatworms.

Flatworms do not consist of a succession of more or less identical metamers (sequential segments) placed behind each other. But they do consist of two antimers (counterparts) :   These are parts lying next to each other, and are – in the case of Flatworms – their right and left body halves. When such a flatworm is divided through its median plane (i.e. when the body halves – antimers – are separated from each other), then each antimer develops into a whole animal again, now again consisting of two antimers. See next Figure.

Figure 1.   The regeneration of a complete flatworm ( of the genus Planaria ), cut as indicated on the left.
( Redrawn after SHELDRAKE, R., 1988, The Presence of the Past (
Morphic Resonance and the Habits of Nature), Figure 5.3, p. 77. )



Higher animals -- "animalia perfecta" in the treatise -- lack such a idem specie divisibility. They are, to be sure, divisible, but the several beings resulting from division are not conspecific with the initial form anymore.

In the mentioned treatise a metaphysical explanation is attemted in Chapter 9, the investigation of which I would like to postpone for the time being.
Important and interesting however is that such a divisibility, which does not preserve specific identity, does not relate to 'height' (in the sense of being a higher organism) of the being in question, as is asserted in the treatise, because this phenomenon also occurs in the case of molecules, existing on their own, i.e. not in one or another repetitional frame, but freely in gasses or in non-ionizing solvents. It appears inevitable to me that molecules (which as such were not known in the Middle Ages, at most in the form of the theoretical minima) must be considered as Substances.
The impossibility of idem specie division seems to me to be related to the degree of unity of the thing in question. This unity is strong in the case of a molecule, weaker in the case of a crystal, and strong again in the case of higher organisms. The unity of a human being is actual, and he does not possess a potential multitude idem specie within himself [NOTE 2], while this is the case with crystals, but absent again in the case of molecules. If we divide the latter, then we get specifically different products.
Strong unity, as can be observed in the case of organisms, returns in the submicroscopical domain.

Coherent with the Totality character of a Substance is the way of being of the elements in the mixtum perfectum ( In the mixtum imperfectum, the mixture, the aggregate, the way of being of the elements is always an actual one).

Let us discuss the meaning of the following expression :

The conservation of (some) properties of the elements in the mixtum

Expressed in this way it is a low-level consideration. The corresponding high-level consideration is as follows :

In the mixtum perfectum, once formed, the conserved properties do not originate from a simultaneous presence of the qualities of the elements. The 'average' quality (i.e. how it behaves, and looks like) of the mixtum originates from the (one) Form of the mixtum. Nevertheless it displays a similarity with some properties of the elements, in virtue of the 'genetic' kinship of the mixtum and its elements (After all, the mixtum originated physically from the elements). The elements themselves are present only in a virtual way (i.e. in a near potency to those elements), so also some of their properties. These properties have now become properties of the mixtum, they are generic propria (i.e. they are properties, typical for a particular genus).
Genuinely new properties of such a real mixtum can be considered as a Totality-resultant.

Precisely such a type of Totality must be demanded, if one assumes that every Substance possesses only one substantial form.
At first sight this is a completely different way of seeing things than the one by which we see the mixtum as a Whole that is generated by the interaction of the parts, i.e. a strong interaction such that the parts display an intrinsically organized connection leading to the Totality in question. But we can, as already suggested, interpret this formulation as a low-level consideration, i.e. a consideration at the level of the elements, of which some properties are conserved.
The (above) high-level description departs from (i.e. starts with) the mixtum : the elements are exclusively considered in their relation to the mixtum. It is only the mixtum that IS. The way of being (the way of being present) of the elements is virtual. However this virtual way of being of the elements (the parts of the mixtum) is hard to harmonize with their activity. In the case of crystals this activity is minor, but in the case of organisms there is a strong cooperative interaction of parts, and then the continuum view becomes problematic.
So it seems better to let the virtuality of the elements depend on the type of consideration : The elements are present in the mixtum in an actual state (in which interaction is possible) within a low-level consideration, while they are only virtually present in the mixtum, within a high-level consideration. The mentioned activity of the elements would then have to be interpreted as the activity of the mixtum. With all this we anticipate a treatment of such levels in a special Essay later on.
The high-level consideration can, as is said earlier, ascribe a character of causality to the Form of the mixtum (its substantial form) because the elements, in their interactions, are directed to the Whole (the particular individual mixtum) in virtue of which this Whole is, in a sense, already, 'presupposed' by its parts. Such a holistic behavior is indeed observable with respect to a number of mixta, for example :
When the lens of a newt's eye is removed surgically, then a new lens is being regenerated from the margin of the iris. The remarkable fact is that the lens is formed in the normal embryological development in a completely different way, namely from skin tissue. Because of the purely artificial character of the surgical maiming, this capacity for regeneration cannot have been developed evolutionarily -- through natural selection, because such an event never happens in Nature (See SHELDRAKE, R., 1981, A new science of life, p. 24/25, in Paladin Books, 1987 ). In this case it is clear that the parts are directed towards the Whole, i.e. they presuppose that Whole (But see NOTE 3).
Also in the case of crystals we can observe an accelerated healing of injury, during the growth of a crystal, that is deliberately damaged.
The Whole has -- as we could express ourselves -- a substantial form which acts in a guiding, controlling way on the parts.

In the case of a genuine Aggregate the properties of that aggregate are the properties of the elements (additive properties, like the weight of that aggegate), unless we have to do with emergent aggregation-resultants (like the blue of the sky). These are not just the result of the 'many-ness' of the element particles, but of a many-ness exceeding a certain more or less critical value, giving rise to new properties. These properties however derive, just like that, from the presence of that multitude of element particles, i.e. they derive wholly from that multitude of element particles.
Further examples of emergent aggregation-resultants are : temperature, and pressure. They only appear in the case of larger quantities of matter, hence from larger numbers of aggregate elements. They are constitutive properties of the aggregate. So we have :

  1. Additive properties, like mass, weight, electrical charge, etc. These properties are also present at the level of the elements.
  2. Emergent aggregation-resultants, properties that are not present at the level of the elements, like temperature. They originate however totally from the composing (and interacting) elements.
The counterpart of 2. should be :
  1. Emergent properties, that do not originate just like that from the 'being-togetherness' of the elements. These are totality-resultants, which we encounter in the case of Totalities, in contrast to aggregates. These totality-resultants are not reducible to the interplay of the elements, because within a Totality these elements are only virtually present, at any rate within Thomism.
But do such totality-resultants really exist? (We have discussed this also in the STATUS QUAESTIONIS, in connection with the work of HOENEN)
Indeed one cannot, with respect to most mixta, calculate the properties, which specifically belong to the mixtum -- which characterize the mixtum -- precisely (i.e. quantum mechanically) from the (properties of the) elements.
But, is this an impossibility in principle, or is it based on insufficient knowledge of those elements and the absence (for the time being) of the appropriate mathematical methods?
Only if the mentioned impossibility is a matter of a principle, we have to do with real totality-resultants (in contradistinction with aggregation-resultants). Such totality-resultants are demanded by the assumption of only ONE substantial form in each Substance.
Personally I am inclined to assume that the mentioned impossibility of exact prediction of the characteristic properties of the mixtum is not a matter of principle, and if this is correct, then the mixta in question are not genuine continua, but organized contigua. Such a contiguum is a totality type different from a genuine continuum.
The above mentioned holistic phenomena, like the regeneration of the eye lens of the newt, seem, for the time being, to contradict this however. In these cases the Whole seems prior to the parts. Perhaps the Whole (the Totality in question) cannot afterall be calculated from the parts, i.e. be exactly predicted, even (not so) in principle. And this implies that this Whole cannot exhaustively be understood from the parts, which could mean that this Whole is not totally comprised within its parts, i.e. it is not just the sum of its parts.

Organic Mixta

In In VII Met., lectio 16, nr. 1634--1636 (See the quotation of this text above) St Thomas speaks about organic mixta. There the parts are also, it is true, just potentially existing (and only as such they are parts), but they are in a near (in contrast to a remote) potency to their act(uality). And this because of the fact that the living bodies are organic bodies (i.e. 'mechanical' bodies) which have formally distinguished parts. So the problem to interpret an organism -- which, consequently, comprises moving parts -- as a continuum nevertheless, St Thomas here solves by posing that the potentiality of the parts is a near potentiality, near to its proper act(uality).
However this, according to me, should also hold for the inorganic mixta, where, namely, the elements are also near to their act, which is evident when we compose such a mixtum and then decompose it again. And especially this will be true if we assume organisms and inorganisms to be ontologically equivalent -- with a difference in degree only, be it a fairly great (gradual) difference -- because, according to modern insights, organisms have (ultimately) developed from inorganisms in a natural way.
Despite the proximity of the potentiality of the elements (the parts) -- and this is called their being virtual -- the parts remain potential just like that (also according to St Thomas in nr. 1636) if, according to St Thomas in that text, the Whole is one and continuous in nature. He distinguishes this from cases like grafting of plants, where a continuum results too, but not in a natural way. Today, as I see it, we don't need to make such a distinction anymore.
An organism is thus according to St Thomas a continuum, the parts of which exist only virtually.
The next Figure visualizes such virtual parts in the case of moving parts. Virtual parts are in fact not parts but qualities.

Figure 1. Visualization of a moving part that is virtual, and consequently a quality. Movement of virtual parts generally is a continuous redistribution of qualities within the Totality. Here one such quality (red) is shown (against a background quality (grey)), as it shifts from left to right. This shift of the quality is not a movement but an ongoing replacement.

Those virtual parts exist however in a near potency to their act, as has been said, and we should (thematically) investigate what this should mean precisely. For how can something act, i.e. (constantly) execute its function (like the beating of the heart), when it exists only potential (even if it is a near potence)?
A possible consideration is : that an organism is not a genuine continuum after all, but a tight, organized contiguum, in contrast with, say, a granite pebble, which is a genuine aggregate (of crystals), and so not an organized contiguum.
What could be the metaphysical implications of such an assumption?




back to homepage

****************